Continuous at Every Rational Discontinuous at Every Irrational

Function that is discontinuous at rationals and continuous at irrationals

Point plot on the interval (0,1). The topmost point in the middle shows f(1/2) = 1/2

Thomae's function is a real-valued function of a real variable that can be defined as:[1]

f ( x ) = { 1 q if x = p q ( x  is rational), with p Z  and q N  coprime 0 if x  is irrational. {\displaystyle f(x)={\begin{cases}{\frac {1}{q}}&{\text{if }}x={\tfrac {p}{q}}\quad (x{\text{ is rational), with }}p\in \mathbb {Z} {\text{ and }}q\in \mathbb {N} {\text{ coprime}}\\0&{\text{if }}x{\text{ is irrational.}}\end{cases}}}

It is named after Carl Johannes Thomae, but has many other names: the popcorn function, the raindrop function, the countable cloud function, the modified Dirichlet function, the ruler function,[2] the Riemann function, or the Stars over Babylon (John Horton Conway's name).[3] Thomae mentioned it as an example for an integrable function with infinitely many discontinuities in an early textbook on Riemann's notion of integration.[4]

Since every rational number has a unique representation with coprime (also termed relatively prime) p Z {\displaystyle p\in \mathbb {Z} } and q N {\displaystyle q\in \mathbb {N} } , the function is well-defined. Note that q = + 1 {\displaystyle q=+1} is the only number in N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } that is coprime to p = 0. {\displaystyle p=0.}

It is a modification of the Dirichlet function, which is 1 at rational numbers and 0 elsewhere.

Properties [edit]

Proof of periodicity

For all x R Q , {\displaystyle x\in \mathbb {R} \smallsetminus \mathbb {Q} ,} we also have x + n R Q {\displaystyle x+n\in \mathbb {R} \smallsetminus \mathbb {Q} } and hence f ( x + n ) = f ( x ) = 0 , {\displaystyle f(x+n)=f(x)=0,}

For all x Q , {\displaystyle x\in \mathbb {Q} ,\;} there exist p Z {\displaystyle p\in \mathbb {Z} } and q N {\displaystyle q\in \mathbb {N} } such that x = p / q , {\displaystyle \;x=p/q,\;} and gcd ( p , q ) = 1. {\displaystyle \gcd(p,\;q)=1.} Consider x + n = ( p + n q ) / q {\displaystyle x+n=(p+nq)/q} . If d {\displaystyle d} divides p {\displaystyle p} and q {\displaystyle q} , it divides p + n q {\displaystyle p+nq} and q {\displaystyle q} . Conversely, if d {\displaystyle d} divides p + n q {\displaystyle p+nq} and q {\displaystyle q} , it divides ( p + n q ) n q = p {\displaystyle (p+nq)-nq=p} and q {\displaystyle q} . So gcd ( p + n q , q ) = gcd ( p , q ) = 1 {\displaystyle \gcd(p+nq,q)=\gcd(p,q)=1} , and f ( x + n ) = 1 / q = f ( x ) {\displaystyle f(x+n)=1/q=f(x)} .

  • f {\displaystyle f} is discontinuous at all rational numbers, dense within the real numbers.

Proof of discontinuity at rational numbers

Let x 0 = p / q {\displaystyle x_{0}=p/q} be an arbitrary rational number, with p Z , q N , {\displaystyle \;p\in \mathbb {Z} ,\;q\in \mathbb {N} ,} and p {\displaystyle p} and q {\displaystyle q} coprime.

This establishes f ( x 0 ) = 1 / q . {\displaystyle f(x_{0})=1/q.}

Let α R Q {\displaystyle \;\alpha \in \mathbb {R} \smallsetminus \mathbb {Q} \;} be any irrational number and define x n = x 0 + α n {\displaystyle x_{n}=x_{0}+{\frac {\alpha }{n}}} for all n N . {\displaystyle n\in \mathbb {N} .}

These x n {\displaystyle x_{n}} are all irrational, and so f ( x n ) = 0 {\displaystyle f(x_{n})=0} for all n N . {\displaystyle n\in \mathbb {N} .}

This implies | x 0 x n | = α n , {\displaystyle |x_{0}-x_{n}|={\frac {\alpha }{n}},\quad } and | f ( x 0 ) f ( x n ) | = 1 q . {\displaystyle \quad |f(x_{0})-f(x_{n})|={\frac {1}{q}}.}

Let ε = 1 / q {\displaystyle \;\varepsilon =1/q\;} , and given δ > 0 {\displaystyle \delta >0} let n = 1 + α δ . {\displaystyle n=1+\left\lceil {\frac {\alpha }{\delta }}\right\rceil .} For the corresponding x n {\displaystyle \;x_{n}} we have

| f ( x 0 ) f ( x n ) | = 1 / q ε {\displaystyle |f(x_{0})-f(x_{n})|=1/q\geq \varepsilon \quad } and

| x 0 x n | = α n = α 1 + α δ < α α δ δ , {\displaystyle |x_{0}-x_{n}|={\frac {\alpha }{n}}={\frac {\alpha }{1+\left\lceil {\frac {\alpha }{\delta }}\right\rceil }}<{\frac {\alpha }{\left\lceil {\frac {\alpha }{\delta }}\right\rceil }}\leq \delta ,}

which is exactly the definition of discontinuity of f {\displaystyle f} at x 0 {\displaystyle x_{0}} .

  • f {\displaystyle f} is continuous at all irrational numbers, also dense within the real numbers.

Proof of continuity at irrational arguments

Since f {\displaystyle f} is periodic with period 1 {\displaystyle 1} and 0 Q , {\displaystyle 0\in \mathbb {Q} ,} it suffices to check all irrational points in I = ( 0 , 1 ) . {\displaystyle I=(0,\;1).\;} Assume now ε > 0 , i N {\displaystyle \varepsilon >0,\;i\in \mathbb {N} } and x 0 I Q . {\displaystyle x_{0}\in I\smallsetminus \mathbb {Q} .} According to the Archimedean property of the reals, there exists r N {\displaystyle r\in \mathbb {N} } with 1 / r < ε , {\displaystyle 1/r<\varepsilon ,} and there exist k i N , {\displaystyle \;k_{i}\in \mathbb {N} ,} such that

for i = 1 , , r {\displaystyle i=1,\ldots ,r} we have 0 < k i i < x 0 < k i + 1 i . {\displaystyle 0<{\frac {k_{i}}{i}}<x_{0}<{\frac {k_{i}+1}{i}}.}

The minimal distance of x 0 {\displaystyle x_{0}} to its i-th lower and upper bounds equals

d i := min { | x 0 k i i | , | x 0 k i + 1 i | } . {\displaystyle d_{i}:=\min \left\{\left|x_{0}-{\frac {k_{i}}{i}}\right|,\;\left|x_{0}-{\frac {k_{i}+1}{i}}\right|\right\}.}

We define δ {\displaystyle \delta } as the minimum of all the finitely many d i . {\displaystyle d_{i}.}

δ := min 1 i r { d i } , {\displaystyle \delta :=\min _{1\leq i\leq r}\{d_{i}\},\;} so that

for all i = 1 , . . . , r , {\displaystyle i=1,...,r,} | x 0 k i / i | δ {\displaystyle \quad |x_{0}-k_{i}/i|\geq \delta \quad } and | x 0 ( k i + 1 ) / i | δ . {\displaystyle \quad |x_{0}-(k_{i}+1)/i|\geq \delta .}

This is to say, all these rational numbers k i / i , ( k i + 1 ) / i , {\displaystyle k_{i}/i,\;(k_{i}+1)/i,\;} are outside the δ {\displaystyle \delta } -neighborhood of x 0 . {\displaystyle x_{0}.}

Now let x Q ( x 0 δ , x 0 + δ ) {\displaystyle x\in \mathbb {Q} \cap (x_{0}-\delta ,x_{0}+\delta )} with the unique representation x = p / q {\displaystyle x=p/q} where p , q N {\displaystyle p,q\in \mathbb {N} } are coprime. Then, necessarily, q > r , {\displaystyle q>r,\;} and therefore,

f ( x ) = 1 / q < 1 / r < ε . {\displaystyle f(x)=1/q<1/r<\varepsilon .}

Likewise, for all irrational x I , f ( x ) = 0 = f ( x 0 ) , {\displaystyle x\in I,\;f(x)=0=f(x_{0}),\;} and thus, if ε > 0 {\displaystyle \varepsilon >0} then any choice of (sufficiently small) δ > 0 {\displaystyle \delta >0} gives

| x x 0 | < δ | f ( x 0 ) f ( x ) | = f ( x ) < ε . {\displaystyle |x-x_{0}|<\delta \implies |f(x_{0})-f(x)|=f(x)<\varepsilon .}

Therefore, f {\displaystyle f} is continuous on R Q . {\displaystyle \mathbb {R} \smallsetminus \mathbb {Q} .\quad }

  • f {\displaystyle f} is nowhere differentiable.

Proof of being nowhere differentiable

  • For rational numbers, this follows from non-continuity.
  • For irrational numbers:
For any sequence of irrational numbers ( a n ) n = 1 {\displaystyle (a_{n})_{n=1}^{\infty }} with a n x 0 {\displaystyle a_{n}\neq x_{0}} for all n N + {\displaystyle n\in \mathbb {N} _{+}} that converges to the irrational point x 0 , {\displaystyle x_{0},\;} the sequence ( f ( a n ) ) n = 1 {\displaystyle (f(a_{n}))_{n=1}^{\infty }} is identically 0 , {\displaystyle 0,\;} and so lim n | f ( a n ) f ( x 0 ) a n x 0 | = 0. {\displaystyle \lim _{n\to \infty }\left|{\frac {f(a_{n})-f(x_{0})}{a_{n}-x_{0}}}\right|=0.}
According to Hurwitz's theorem, there also exists a sequence of rational numbers ( b n ) n = 1 = ( k n / n ) n = 1 , {\displaystyle (b_{n})_{n=1}^{\infty }=(k_{n}/n)_{n=1}^{\infty },\;} converging to x 0 , {\displaystyle x_{0},\;} with k n Z {\displaystyle k_{n}\in \mathbb {Z} } and n N {\displaystyle n\in \mathbb {N} } coprime and | k n / n x 0 | < 1 5 n 2 . {\displaystyle |k_{n}/n-x_{0}|<{\frac {1}{{\sqrt {5}}\cdot n^{2}}}.\;}
Thus for all n , {\displaystyle n,} | f ( b n ) f ( x 0 ) b n x 0 | > 1 / n 0 1 / ( 5 n 2 ) = 5 n 0 {\displaystyle \left|{\frac {f(b_{n})-f(x_{0})}{b_{n}-x_{0}}}\right|>{\frac {1/n-0}{1/({\sqrt {5}}\cdot n^{2})}}={\sqrt {5}}\cdot n\neq 0\;} and so f {\displaystyle f} is not differentiable at all irrational x 0 . {\displaystyle x_{0}.}
  • f {\displaystyle f} has a strict local maximum at each rational number.[ citation needed ]
See the proofs for continuity and discontinuity above for the construction of appropriate neighbourhoods, where f {\displaystyle f} has maxima.
The Lebesgue criterion for integrability states that a bounded function is Riemann integrable if and only if the set of all discontinuities has measure zero.[5] Every countable subset of the real numbers - such as the rational numbers - has measure zero, so the above discussion shows that Thomae's function is Riemann integrable on any interval. The function's integral is equal to 0 {\displaystyle 0} over any set because the function is equal to zero almost everywhere.

[edit]

Empirical probability distributions related to Thomae's function appear in DNA sequencing.[7] The human genome is diploid, having two strands per chromosome. When sequenced, small pieces ("reads") are generated: for each spot on the genome, an integer number of reads overlap with it. Their ratio is a rational number, and typically distributed similarly to Thomae's function.

If pairs of positive integers m , n {\displaystyle m,n} are sampled from a distribution f ( n , m ) {\displaystyle f(n,m)} and used to generate ratios q = n / ( n + m ) {\displaystyle q=n/(n+m)} , this gives rise to a distribution g ( q ) {\displaystyle g(q)} on the rational numbers. If the integers are independent the distribution can be viewed as a convolution over the rational numbers, g ( a / ( a + b ) ) = t = 1 f ( t a ) f ( t b ) {\textstyle g(a/(a+b))=\sum _{t=1}^{\infty }f(ta)f(tb)} . Closed form solutions exist for power-law distributions with a cut-off. If f ( k ) = k α e β k / L i α ( e β ) {\displaystyle f(k)=k^{-\alpha }e^{-\beta k}/\mathrm {Li} _{\alpha }(e^{-\beta })} (where L i α {\displaystyle \mathrm {Li} _{\alpha }} is the polylogarithm function) then g ( a / ( a + b ) ) = ( a b ) α L i 2 α ( e ( a + b ) β ) / L i α 2 ( e β ) {\displaystyle g(a/(a+b))=(ab)^{-\alpha }\mathrm {Li} _{2\alpha }(e^{-(a+b)\beta })/\mathrm {Li} _{\alpha }^{2}(e^{-\beta })} . In the case of uniform distributions on the set { 1 , 2 , , L } {\displaystyle \{1,2,\ldots ,L\}} g ( a / ( a + b ) ) = ( 1 / L 2 ) L / max ( a , b ) {\displaystyle g(a/(a+b))=(1/L^{2})\lfloor L/\max(a,b)\rfloor } , which is very similar to Thomae's function.[7]

The ruler function [edit]

For integers, the exponent of the highest power of 2 dividing n {\displaystyle n} gives 0, 1, 0, 2, 0, 1, 0, 3, 0, 1, 0, 2, 0, 1, 0, ... (sequence A007814 in the OEIS). If 1 is added, or if the 0s are removed, 1, 2, 1, 3, 1, 2, 1, 4, 1, 2, 1, 3, 1, 2, 1, ... (sequence A001511 in the OEIS). The values resemble tick-marks on a 1/16th graduated ruler, hence the name. These values correspond to the restriction of the Thomae function to the dyadic rationals: those rational numbers whose denominators are powers of 2.

[edit]

A natural follow-up question one might ask is if there is a function which is continuous on the rational numbers and discontinuous on the irrational numbers. This turns out to be impossible. The set of discontinuities of any function must be an F σ set. If such a function existed, then the irrationals would be an F σ set. The irrationals would then be the countable union of closed sets i = 0 C i {\displaystyle \textstyle \bigcup _{i=0}^{\infty }C_{i}} , but since the irrationals do not contain an interval, neither can any of the C i {\displaystyle C_{i}} . Therefore, each of the C i {\displaystyle C_{i}} would be nowhere dense, and the irrationals would be a meager set. It would follow that the real numbers, being the union of the irrationals and the rationals (which, as a countable set, is evidently meager), would also be a meager set. This would contradict the Baire category theorem: because the reals form a complete metric space, they form a Baire space, which cannot be meager in itself.

A variant of Thomae's function can be used to show that any F σ subset of the real numbers can be the set of discontinuities of a function. If A = n = 1 F n {\displaystyle A=\textstyle \bigcup _{n=1}^{\infty }F_{n}} is a countable union of closed sets F n {\displaystyle F_{n}} , define

f A ( x ) = { 1 n if x  is rational and n  is minimal so that x F n 1 n if x  is irrational and n  is minimal so that x F n 0 if x A {\displaystyle f_{A}(x)={\begin{cases}{\frac {1}{n}}&{\text{if }}x{\text{ is rational and }}n{\text{ is minimal so that }}x\in F_{n}\\-{\frac {1}{n}}&{\text{if }}x{\text{ is irrational and }}n{\text{ is minimal so that }}x\in F_{n}\\0&{\text{if }}x\notin A\end{cases}}}

Then a similar argument as for Thomae's function shows that f A {\displaystyle f_{A}} has A as its set of discontinuities.

See also [edit]

  • Blumberg theorem
  • Cantor function
  • Dirichlet function
  • Euclid's orchard – Thomae's function can be interpreted as a perspective drawing of Euclid's orchard
  • Volterra's function

Notes [edit]

  1. ^ Beanland, Roberts & Stevenson 2009, p. 531
  2. ^ "…the so-called ruler function, a simple but provocative example that appeared in a work of Johannes Karl Thomae … The graph suggests the vertical markings on a ruler—hence the name." (Dunham 2008, p. 149, chapter 10)
  3. ^ John Conway. "Topic: Provenance of a function". The Math Forum. Archived from the original on 13 June 2018.
  4. ^ Thomae 1875, p. 14, §20
  5. ^ Spivak 1965, p. 53, Theorem 3-8
  6. ^ Chen, Haipeng; Fraser, Jonathan M.; Yu, Han (2022). "Dimensions of the popcorn graph". Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society. 150 (11): 4729–4742. arXiv:2007.08407. doi:10.1090/proc/15729.
  7. ^ a b Trifonov, Vladimir; Pasqualucci, Laura; Dalla-Favera, Riccardo; Rabadan, Raul (2011). "Fractal-like Distributions over the Rational Numbers in High-throughput Biological and Clinical Data". Scientific Reports. 1 (191): 191. arXiv:1010.4328. Bibcode:2011NatSR...1E.191T. doi:10.1038/srep00191. PMC3240948. PMID 22355706.

References [edit]

  • Thomae, J. (1875), Einleitung in die Theorie der bestimmten Integrale (in German), Halle a/S: Verlag von Louis Nebert
  • Abbott, Stephen (2016), Understanding Analysis (Softcover reprint of the original 2nd ed.), New York: Springer, ISBN978-1-4939-5026-3
  • Bartle, Robert G.; Sherbert, Donald R. (1999), Introduction to Real Analysis (3rd ed.), Wiley, ISBN978-0-471-32148-4 (Example 5.1.6 (h))
  • Beanland, Kevin; Roberts, James W.; Stevenson, Craig (2009), "Modifications of Thomae's Function and Differentiability", The American Mathematical Monthly, 116 (6): 531–535, doi:10.4169/193009709x470425, JSTOR 40391145
  • Dunham, William (2008), The Calculus Gallery: Masterpieces from Newton to Lebesgue (Paperback ed.), Princeton: Princeton University Press, ISBN978-0-691-13626-4
  • Spivak, M. (1965), Calculus on manifolds, Perseus Books, ISBN978-0-8053-9021-6

External links [edit]

  • "Dirichlet-function", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, EMS Press, 2001 [1994]
  • Weisstein, Eric W. "Dirichlet Function". MathWorld.

ibarradoomad.blogspot.com

Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Thomae%27s_function

0 Response to "Continuous at Every Rational Discontinuous at Every Irrational"

Post a Comment

Iklan Atas Artikel

Iklan Tengah Artikel 1

Iklan Tengah Artikel 2

Iklan Bawah Artikel